The icon indicates free access to the linked research on JSTOR.

Is it right to punish someone for a crime they don’t remember committing? Is it wrong to punish someone for a crime they remember, but didn’t commit? How we answer these questions illuminates our intuitions about the relationship between memory and personal identity.

JSTOR Teaching ResourcesJSTOR Teaching Resources

The television show Black Mirror explores these quandaries in the season two crescendo, “White Bear” (spoilers ahead). This episode documents the cruel and unusual punishment inflicted on the protagonist, an amnesiac named Victoria who awakens in a dystopian reality with no recollection of how she got there. For most of the episode, Victoria is physically and psychologically tormented, made to believe she is being hunted while bystanders document her murder.

Near the end of the story, we learn that Victoria is an inmate in a prison-amusement park hybrid, where she is punished by actors and paying visitors for her role in documenting the murder of a child. Her boyfriend killed a six-year-old girl while she filmed. Finally, Victoria remembers the crime and comprehends the nature of her punishment, a techno-futurist application of Hammurabi’s Code.

But she doesn’t get long to reflect on her crimes; using mind-wipe technology, the authorities clear her memories to prepare Victoria for a fresh round of Sisyphean punishment.

That memory wipe is truly horrifying. Without the memory of her crime, it seems that, at a fundamental level, the Victoria that is being punished isn’t the same person as the Victoria that committed the crime. This is not to imply that you can only be held accountable for things you remember doing. There are still ways in which a person can be culpable and should be punished for acts they don’t remember, like someone who assaults a bar patron while blackout drunk.

What is striking about the purported justice of “White Bear” is the immense cruelty of tormenting someone who believed herself innocent. The memory-wiped version of Victoria, it seems, was effectively reset to the person she was before she committed her crime. On this view of personal identity, memory is, while not a necessary and sufficient condition for what makes you you, a key part.

This isn’t a quagmire confined to sci-fi dystopias. Rachel Aviv’s New Yorker piece, “Remembering The Murder You Didn’t Commit,” addresses the inverse of the question raised by “White Bear.” Aviv recounts the tragedy of six people sent to prison for the rape and murder of an old woman. Decades later, they were pardoned after DNA evidence exonerated them; a strange twist given the conditions of their conviction. Five of the six had confessed. Despite being factually innocent, one of the people who confessed still harbors memories of the murder she didn’t commit—tactile flashbacks, her fingers on the pillowcase that smothered the victim. Another maintains her guilt to this day.

* * *

Is it wrong to punish someone for a crime they remember, but didn’t commit? The intuitive answer seems clear: absolutely not. But my intuitions, at least, are drawn and quartered by these questions. On one hand, it seems wrong to punish a criminal if they don’t remember the crime, because in some important mental sense, the person being punished didn’t commit the crime. On the other hand, it seems wrong to punish an innocent person for a crime they do remember, because in some important physical sense, they didn’t commit the crime.

Obviously, memory is not the only consideration when assigning blame and punishment. But our thoughts about these cases betray our feelings about personal identity. One theory of personal identity holds that the concept is, in large part, built upon experiences and memories. In western philosophy, this memory theory of personal identity goes back to John Locke (or Spinoza, depending on who you ask). The law, however, doesn’t consider “personal identities,” but persons. Can these ideas be cleanly separated?

This is the problem faced by the legal system in cases where the defendant has Dissociative Identity Disorder (DID) and the alleged crime was committed by the non-dominant identity. To punish the criminal, you would have to punish all of the identities that occupy their body. As the philosophers Walter Sinnott-Armstrong and Stephen Benke have argued, however, overreliance on personal identity in determining culpability just muddies the waters. What’s important to them is the mental state of the person at the time of the crime. Could the perpetrator reasonably have been expected to understand their actions?

It’s inevitable that when these cases end in punishment, we are faced with the same dilemma as Victoria in “White Bear.” Without memory of the crimes committed by their alters, criminally responsible DID patients still face the disturbing disconnect between their personal identity and personal responsibility.

And while DID is rare, it isn’t the only mental factor than can obscure relevant memories. A more salient example can be found in the made-for-television movie and candidate for Best Title, B-Movie Category, The Sleepwalker Killing. The film was inspired by Canadian Kenneth Parks, who murdered his mother-in-law while sleepwalking. Parks was acquitted of the crime, because the judge deemed him to be entirely lacking in self-control at the time of his misdeeds. The moral appraisal is that, although sleeping Parks is a murderer, conscious Parks is not.

That’s not a contradiction: In terms of personal identity, memory can play an important role in instantiating who you are at every instant. The amount of time it takes for someone to tell you that you have cancer, that a nuclear war is about to begin, that you’ve committed a murder in your sleep, can radically shift your personal identity. Some philosophers, like Peter Goldie, argue that this tells us more about our capacity for narrative thinking than our reliance on memory—we just happen to incorporate memories into our narratives.

But even with this emphasis on narrative thinking, memory still plays an important role. And this can be problematic, given the fragile nature of our memories. As the philosopher and cognitive psychologist Elizabeth Loftus has demonstrated, not only can our memories be invented, they can be implanted.

* * *

Which leads me to wonder… what if some of my foundational memories are fabricated? The ones that inform my values, give me purpose and meaning, situate me in the world?

If I ask you whether or not you are good at math, you will reflect upon your past experiences of adding, subtracting, evaluating cosine functions, maybe calculating differentials. It is in light of these experiences, these memories, that you consider yourself to be good—or bad—at math.

It’s no different with traits that are more important to your personal identity than math skills. If I ask you if you’re a vengeful person, you will probably search through your experiences to find situations where you have behaved vengefully and mercifully. Add in a new memory, and your answer may change, because your narrative, and your personal identity, has changed. Identity is, on this telling, a chain of memories and dispositions, continuous but mutable, always yours but never identical to what it was.

Resources

JSTOR is a digital library for scholars, researchers, and students. JSTOR Daily readers can access the original research behind our articles for free on JSTOR.

Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 35, No. 2 (Jun., 2005), pp. 243-268
Canadian Journal of Philosophy
Scientific American Mind, Vol. 23, No. 3 (July/August 2012), pp. 38-41
Scientific American, a division of Nature America, Inc.
The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 67, No. 1, Special Issue: The Poetics, Aesthetics, and Philosophy of Narrative (Winter, 2009), pp. 97-106
Wiley on behalf of The American Society for Aesthetics
Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, Vol. 142, No. 1 (Mar., 1998), pp. 60-73
American Philosophical Society